måndag 31 mars 2025

TIPS FOR LIVING WITH A MASSIVE PENIS

Author: Richard M. Downs
Year: 2024
Publisher: Membrum Virile Press
Language: English


Finally made you click the link! 
Have a wonderful April Fools' Day. May the sun shine on your smiling face, today and always.  


 

söndag 23 mars 2025

DRIVE YOUR PLOW OVER THE BONES OF THE DEAD

Author: Olga Tokarczuk
Year: 2016 (2009)
Publisher: Wydawnictwo Literackie
Language: Polish

Polish writer Olga Tokarczuk is one of a handful of writers that I was familiar with before they were awarded the Nobel Prize in literature. I have also previously shared some thoughts on her writing on my blog (see review of “Tales of the Bizarre” from January 2020). One of her most famous titles, and for many Swedes the entry point into her literary output, is “Prowadź swój pług przez kości umarłych” (“Drive Your Plow Over the Bones of the Dead”). This novel presents a narrative that intertwines themes of justice, accountability, and the nature of existence, enveloped in a murder mystery, all through the perspective of Janina, an eccentric and reclusive woman living in a remote village in the Polish mountains.

At the heart of Janina’s existence is a profound sense of alienation. She is an outsider in the community, not just because of her eccentricities and lifestyle but also because of her unconventional moral beliefs. Her deep empathy for animals and her insistence on treating them as equals to humans, including ascribing them the ability to plan and execute elaborate coordinated acts of passion, create a worldview that sharply contrasts with the dominant human-centric perspective of the other characters in the novel.

This alienation can perhaps be understood as a defence mechanism in the sense that it is a way of protecting herself from the disillusionment of a society that has failed to acknowledge the deeper, more empathetic layers of existence. Her past as a successful architect is only hinted at and when it is, only in the meaning of her falling out of favour and choosing to seclude herself from society.

Janina’s second obsession is with astrology. At first glance, this seems to emphasise her commitment to the idea of a unified universe or natural cohesion, but it also suggests an unconscious desire for control in an unpredictable and threatening world. She believes that the natural world is governed by a higher, mystical order, one that can be understood through astrology and the signs of nature. This belief can be interpreted as a manifestation of the need for certainty in a disappointing and inexplicable Kosmos, as well as an attempt to find meaning in the randomness of life and death, success and humiliation. Through astrology, she constructs an alternate narrative in which the forces of the universe—rather than the arbitrary and ultimately meaningless cruelty of human beings—are in control.

Above all of this hovers Janina’s problematic views on justice. Despite her conviction that every action is predetermined by the stars and that people have but limited freedom to determine who they become and what choices they make, she is drawn to the idea of accountability, guilt, and retribution. Above all, this is manifested by the novel’s poetic leitmotif “Songs of Innocence and of Experience” by British 18th-century poet William Blake. These poems explore the tension between the innocence of childhood and the corruption of adulthood, the dualities of good and evil, and the human capacity for both creation and destruction. Janina identifies with Blake’s vision of a world that is not simply governed by societal conventions but is in constant conflict between the opposing forces of innocence and corruption. The opposite of innocence is not guilt; it is experience, society, education, and history. Corruption is thus inevitable. Janina’s quest for justice is not grounded in human legal systems but in her own moral code, one that aligns with Blake’s critique of institutionalised power and the systems that fail not only to protect the vulnerable but moreover to preserve innocence to begin with.

This is where equality between humans and other animals ends. Janina never tries to read the horoscope for an animal. She does not judge them for their instincts the way she judges humans for acting upon theirs. The idea of justice echoes throughout Janina's pursuit of a reckoning for the wrongs committed against animals and the natural world. The divide between the human and animal kingdoms is not based on our intellect, technology, language, culture, or society. To Janina, the only dividing factor is mankind’s deviation from innocence.

 


fredag 7 mars 2025

EICHMANN IN JERUSALEM

Author: Hannah Arendt
Year: 1992 (1963)
Publisher: Daidalos
Language: Swedish (Translator Barbro & Ingemar Lundberg)

Hannah Arendt’s “Den banala ondskan” (“Eichmann in Jerusalem”) remains one of the most provocative and intellectually rigorous studies of totalitarianism, moral responsibility, and the nature of evil in the twentieth century. Emerging from Arendt’s coverage of Adolf Eichmann’s 1961 trial in Jerusalem for The New Yorker, the book offers both a historical account of the Nazi bureaucrat’s role in the Holocaust and a profound philosophical meditation on the mechanisms of mass murder. With her penetrating analysis and sharp prose, Arendt delivers a work that continues to spark debate among scholars, ethicists, and political theorists to this day.

At the heart of the book lies Arendt’s groundbreaking thesis of the “banality of evil.” Rather than portraying Eichmann as a monstrous figure driven by ideological fanaticism or sadistic cruelty, she presents him as a disturbingly ordinary bureaucrat, a man whose mindless adherence to duty and legalistic rationalisation enabled his participation in genocidal policies. In Arendt’s view, Eichmann’s moral blindness and lack of critical self-examination, rather than inherent malice, made him a key functionary in the Nazi machinery of death. At the heart of the book lies Arendt’s groundbreaking thesis of the “banality of evil.” Rather than portraying Eichmann as a monstrous figure driven by ideological fanaticism or sadistic cruelty, she presents him as a disturbingly ordinary bureaucrat, a man whose mindless adherence to duty and legalistic rationalisation enabled his participation in genocidal policies.

Arendt’s work is methodically structured, meticulously researched, and philosophically astute. She provides a comprehensive account of Eichmann’s career, from his early days as a functionary in the SS to his central role in organising the logistics of deportation and extermination. At the same time, she does not shy away from critiquing the legal and political dimensions of the trial itself, particularly the use of the Israeli court to serve a broader national and symbolic function. While she acknowledges the necessity of justice, she raises concerns about the legal framework under which Eichmann was prosecuted, particularly the retrospective application of laws and the potential for political instrumentalisation.

Despite its intellectual brilliance, “Den banala ondskan” was met with intense controversy, particularly regarding Arendt’s perceived tone and her discussion of Jewish leadership’s role in the Holocaust.

A more confined but no less interesting area of critique, however, was her engagement with Immanuel Kant’s categorical imperative. Arendt accuses Eichmann of distorting Kant’s idea, arguing that he misapplied the principle in his defence. A more rigorous reading of Kant, however, complicates Arendt’s conclusion, raising the unsettling possibility that Eichmann’s actions were, at least formally, consistent with Kantian ethics.

Arendt asserts that Eichmann invoked Kant’s categorical imperative in bad faith, failing to grasp its fundamental emphasis on moral autonomy. Eichmann claimed that he acted according to duty, submitting to laws that he did not himself create, and he saw his role as implementing the decrees of the Führer rather than exercising independent moral judgment. Arendt dismisses this defence, arguing that Kant’s philosophy demands self-legislation in accordance with universal moral law, rather than blind obedience to external commands. However, this interpretation raises a significant dilemma: Kant’s moral philosophy is famously rigid in its emphasis on duty, and under certain conditions, it may indeed produce the kind of mechanical compliance that Arendt condemns.

In short, Eichmann’s compliance with the categorical imperative was not a matter of genocide, which would hardly be possible to reconcile with Kant’s ideas, but rather of duty and following the law. No single individual can will their own law, but they can will whether to abide by it or not. Willing that the law is universally obeyed seems quite compatible with the categorical imperative.

Many notable thinkers have over the years supported Arendt’s conclusions that a reading of Kant that provides for such heinous acts as the Holocaust is a gross distortion. Carsten Bagge Laustsen and Rasmus Ugilt even go as far as calling it “absurd”. Slavoj Zizek sees it as a circular argument to say that ‘your duty is to do your duty.” Others, like Joshua Halberstam, are less dismissive. For if the act of abiding by the law cannot be elevated to universal law, there seems to be an inherent flaw in our understanding of what law means.

Be it as it will, Arendt’s insights into the bureaucratic nature of modern evil remain profoundly relevant in contemporary discussions of state violence, obedience to authority, and moral responsibility. Her reflections on the dangers of unthinking conformity resonate beyond the historical context of the Holocaust, offering a crucial framework for analysing crimes against humanity in later periods. Including our own era.